pdf version of the entry
Dualism
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/dualism/
from the Winter 2012 Edition of the
Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy
Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen John Perry
Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor
Editorial Board
http://plato.stanford.edu/board.html
Library of Congress Catalog Data
ISSN: 1095-5054
Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem-
bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP
content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized
distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the
SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries,
please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ .
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Copyright
c
2012 by the publisher
The Metaphysics Research Lab
Center for the Study of Language and Information
Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305
Dualism
Copyright
c
2012 by the author
Howard Robinson
All rights reserved.
Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/
Dualism
First published Tue Aug 19, 2003; substantive revision Thu Nov 3, 2011
This entry concerns dualism in the philosophy of mind. The term
‘dualism’ has a variety of uses in the history of thought. In general, the
idea is that, for some particular domain, there are two fundamental kinds
or categories of things or principles. In theology, for example a ‘dualist’ is
someone who believes that Good and Evil—or God and the Devil—are
independent and more or less equal forces in the world. Dualism contrasts
with monism, which is the theory that there is only one fundamental kind,
category of thing or principle; and, rather less commonly, with pluralism,
which is the view that there are many kinds or categories. In the
philosophy of mind, dualism is the theory that the mental and the physical
—or mind and body or mind and brain—are, in some sense, radically
different kinds of thing. Because common sense tells us that there are
physical bodies, and because there is intellectual pressure towards
producing a unified view of the world, one could say that materialist
monism is the ‘default option’. Discussion about dualism, therefore, tends
to start from the assumption of the reality of the physical world, and then
to consider arguments for why the mind cannot be treated as simply part
of that world.
1. The Mind-Body Problem and the History of Dualism
1.1 The Mind-Body Problem
1.2 The History of Dualism
2. Varieties of Dualism: Ontology
2.1 Predicate dualism
2.2 Property Dualism
2.3 Substance Dualism
3. Varieties of Dualism: Interaction
3.1 Interactionism
1
3.2 Epiphenomenalism
3.3 Parallelism
4. Arguments for Dualism
4.1 The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism
4.2 The Argument from Predicate Dualism to Property Dualism
4.3 The Modal Argument
4.4 Arguments from Personal Identity
4.5 The Aristotelian Argument in a Modern Form
5. Problems for Dualism
5.1 The Queerness of the Mental
5.2 The Unity of the Mind
5.2.1 Unity and Bundle Dualism
5.2.2 Unity and Substance Dualism
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
1. The Mind-Body Problem and the History of
Dualism
1.1 The Mind-Body Problem
The mind-body problem is the problem: what is the relationship between
mind and body? Or alternatively: what is the relationship between mental
properties and physical properties?
Humans have (or seem to have) both physical properties and mental
properties. People have (or seem to have)the sort of properties attributed
in the physical sciences. These physical properties include size, weight,
shape, colour, motion through space and time, etc. But they also have (or
Dualism
2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
seem to have) mental properties, which we do not attribute to typical
physical objects These properties involve consciousness (including
perceptual experience, emotional experience, and much else),
intentionality (including beliefs, desires, and much else), and they are
possessed by a subject or a self.
Physical properties are public, in the sense that they are, in principle,
equally observable by anyone. Some physical properties—like those of an
electron—are not directly observable at all, but they are equally available
to all, to the same degree, with scientific equipment and techniques. The
same is not true of mental properties. I may be able to tell that you are in
pain by your behaviour, but only you can feel it directly. Similarly, you
just know how something looks to you, and I can only surmise. Conscious
mental events are private to the subject, who has a privileged access to
them of a kind no-one has to the physical.
The mind-body problem concerns the relationship between these two sets
of properties. The mind-body problem breaks down into a number of
components.
1. The ontological question: what are mental states and what are
physical states? Is one class a subclass of the other, so that all mental
states are physical, or vice versa? Or are mental states and physical
states entirely distinct?
2. The causal question: do physical states influence mental states? Do
mental states influence physical states? If so, how?
Different aspects of the mind-body problem arise for different aspects of
the mental, such as consciousness, intentionality, the self.
3. The problem of consciousness: what is consciousness? How is it
related to the brain and the body?
4. The problem of intentionality: what is intentionality? How is it
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 3
related to the brain and the body?
5. The problem of the self: what is the self? How is it related to the
brain and the body?
Other aspects of the mind-body problem arise for aspects of the physical.
For example:
6. The problem of embodiment: what is it for the mind to be housed in
a body? What is it for a body to belong to a particular subject?
The seemingly intractable nature of these problems have given rise to
many different philosophical views.
Materialist views say that, despite appearances to the contrary, mental
states are just physical states. Behaviourism, functionalism, mind-brain
identity theory and the computational theory of mind are examples of
how materialists attempt to explain how this can be so. The most common
factor in such theories is the attempt to explicate the nature of mind and
consciousness in terms of their ability to directly or indirectly modify
behaviour, but there are versions of materialism that try to tie the mental
to the physical without explicitly explaining the mental in terms of its
behaviour-modifying role. The latter are often grouped together under the
label ‘non-reductive physicalism’, though this label is itself rendered
elusive because of the controversial nature of the term ‘reduction’.
Idealist views say that physical states are really mental. This is because
the physical world is an empirical world and, as such, it is the
intersubjective product of our collective experience.
Dualist views (the subject of this entry) say that the mental and the
physical are both real and neither can be assimilated to the other. For the
various forms that dualism can take and the associated problems, see
below.
Dualism
4 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
In sum, we can say that there is a mind-body problem because both
consciousness and thought, broadly construed, seem very different from
anything physical and there is no convincing consensus on how to build a
satisfactorily unified picture of creatures possessed of both a mind and a
body.
Other entries which concern aspects of the mind-body problem include
(among many others): behaviorism, consciousness, eliminative
materialism, epiphenomenalism, functionalism, identity theory,
intentionality, mental causation, neutral monism, and physicalism.
1.2 History of dualism
In dualism, ‘mind’ is contrasted with ‘body’, but at different times,
different aspects of the mind have been the centre of attention. In the
classical and mediaeval periods, it was the intellect that was thought to be
most obviously resistant to a materialistic account: from Descartes on, the
main stumbling block to materialist monism was supposed to be
‘consciousness’, of which phenomenal consciousness or sensation came
to be considered as the paradigm instance.
The classical emphasis originates in Plato's Phaedo. Plato believed that
the true substances are not physical bodies, which are ephemeral, but the
eternal Forms of which bodies are imperfect copies. These Forms not
only make the world possible, they also make it intelligible, because they
perform the role of universals, or what Frege called ‘concepts'. It is their
connection with intelligibility that is relevant to the philosophy of mind.
Because Forms are the grounds of intelligibility, they are what the
intellect must grasp in the process of understanding. In Phaedo Plato
presents a variety of arguments for the immortality of the soul, but the
one that is relevant for our purposes is that the intellect is immaterial
because Forms are immaterial and intellect must have an affinity with the
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 5
Forms it apprehends (78b4–84b8). This affinity is so strong that the soul
strives to leave the body in which it is imprisoned and to dwell in the
realm of Forms. It may take many reincarnations before this is achieved.
Plato's dualism is not, therefore, simply a doctrine in the philosophy of
mind, but an integral part of his whole metaphysics.
One problem with Plato's dualism was that, though he speaks of the soul
as imprisoned in the body, there is no clear account of what binds a
particular soul to a particular body. Their difference in nature makes the
union a mystery.
Aristotle did not believe in Platonic Forms, existing independently of
their instances. Aristotelian forms (the capital ‘F’ has disappeared with
their standing as autonomous entities) are the natures and properties of
things and exist embodied in those things. This enabled Aristotle to
explain the union of body and soul by saying that the soul is the form of
the body. This means that a particular person's soul is no more than his
nature as a human being. Because this seems to make the soul into a
property of the body, it led many interpreters, both ancient and modern, to
interpret his theory as materialistic. The interpretation of Aristotle's
philosophy of mind—and, indeed, of his whole doctrine of form—
remains as live an issue today as it was immediately after his death
(Robinson 1983 and 1991; Nussbaum 1984; Rorty and Nussbaum, eds,
1992). Nevertheless, the text makes it clear that Aristotle believed that the
intellect, though part of the soul, differs from other faculties in not having
a bodily organ. His argument for this constitutes a more tightly argued
case than Plato's for the immateriality of thought and, hence, for a kind of
dualism. He argued that the intellect must be immaterial because if it
were material it could not receive all forms. Just as the eye, because of its
particular physical nature, is sensitive to light but not to sound, and the
ear to sound and not to light, so, if the intellect were in a physical organ it
could be sensitive only to a restricted range of physical things; but this is
Dualism
6 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
not the case, for we can think about any kind of material object (De
Anima III,4; 429a10–b9). As it does not have a material organ, its activity
must be essentially immaterial.
It is common for modern Aristotelians, who otherwise have a high view
of Aristotle's relevance to modern philosophy, to treat this argument as
being of purely historical interest, and not essential to Aristotle's system
as a whole. They emphasize that he was not a ‘Cartesian’ dualist, because
the intellect is an aspect of the soul and the soul is the form of the body,
not a separate substance. Kenny (1989) argues that Aristotle's theory of
mind as form gives him an account similar to Ryle (1949), for it makes
the soul equivalent to the dispositions possessed by a living body. This
‘anti-Cartesian’ approach to Aristotle arguably ignores the fact that, for
Aristotle, the form is the substance.
These issues might seem to be of purely historical interest. But we shall
see in below, in section 4.5, that this is not so.
The identification of form and substance is a feature of Aristotle's system
that Aquinas effectively exploits in this context, identifying soul, intellect
and form, and treating them as a substance. (See, for example, Aquinas
(1912), Part I, questions 75 and 76.) But though the form (and, hence, the
intellect with which it is identical) are the substance of the human person,
they are not the person itself. Aquinas says that when one addresses
prayers to a saint—other than the Blessed Virgin Mary, who is believed
to retain her body in heaven and is, therefore, always a complete person—
one should say, not, for example, ‘Saint Peter pray for us', but ‘soul of
Saint Peter pray for us'. The soul, though an immaterial substance, is the
person only when united with its body. Without the body, those aspects of
its personal memory that depend on images (which are held to be
corporeal) will be lost.(See Aquinas (1912), Part I, question 89.)
The more modern versions of dualism have their origin in Descartes'
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 7
Meditations, and in the debate that was consequent upon Descartes'
theory. Descartes was a substance dualist. He believed that there were
two kinds of substance: matter, of which the essential property is that it is
spatially extended; and mind, of which the essential property is that it
thinks. Descartes' conception of the relation between mind and body was
quite different from that held in the Aristotelian tradition. For Aristotle,
there is no exact science of matter. How matter behaves is essentially
affected by the form that is in it. You cannot combine just any matter with
any form—you cannot make a knife out of butter, nor a human being out
of paper—so the nature of the matter is a necessary condition for the
nature of the substance. But the nature of the substance does not follow
from the nature of its matter alone: there is no ‘bottom up’ account of
substances. Matter is a determinable made determinate by form. This was
how Aristotle thought that he was able to explain the connection of soul
to body: a particular soul exists as the organizing principle in a particular
parcel of matter.
The belief in the relative indeterminacy of matter is one reason for
Aristotle's rejection of atomism. If matter is atomic, then it is already a
collection of determinate objects in its own right, and it becomes natural
to regard the properties of macroscopic substances as mere summations of
the natures of the atoms.
Although, unlike most of his fashionable contemporaries and immediate
successors, Descartes was not an atomist, he was, like the others, a
mechanist about the properties of matter. Bodies are machines that work
according to their own laws. Except where there are minds interfering
with it, matter proceeds deterministically, in its own right. Where there
are minds requiring to influence bodies, they must work by ‘pulling
levers' in a piece of machinery that already has its own laws of operation.
This raises the question of where those ‘levers' are in the body. Descartes
opted for the pineal gland, mainly because it is not duplicated on both
Dualism
8 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
sides of the brain, so it is a candidate for having a unique, unifying
function.
The main uncertainty that faced Descartes and his contemporaries,
however, was not where interaction took place, but how two things so
different as thought and extension could interact at all. This would be
particularly mysterious if one had an impact view of causal interaction, as
would anyone influenced by atomism, for whom the paradigm of
causation is like two billiard balls cannoning off one another.
Various of Descartes' disciples, such as Arnold Geulincx and Nicholas
Malebranche, concluded that all mind-body interactions required the
direct intervention of God. The appropriate states of mind and body were
only the occasions for such intervention, not real causes. Now it would be
convenient to think that occasionalists held that all causation was natural
except for that between mind and body. In fact they generalized their
conclusion and treated all causation as directly dependent on God. Why
this was so, we cannot discuss here.
Descartes' conception of a dualism of substances came under attack from
the more radical empiricists, who found it difficult to attach sense to the
concept of substance at all. Locke, as a moderate empiricist, accepted that
there were both material and immaterial substances. Berkeley famously
rejected material substance, because he rejected all existence outside the
mind. In his early Notebooks, he toyed with the idea of rejecting
immaterial substance, because we could have no idea of it, and reducing
the self to a collection of the ‘ideas' that constituted its contents. Finally,
he decided that the self, conceived as something over and above the ideas
of which it was aware, was essential for an adequate understanding of the
human person. Although the self and its acts are not presented to
consciousness as objects of awareness, we are obliquely aware of them
simply by dint of being active subjects. Hume rejected such claims, and
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 9
proclaimed the self to be nothing more than a concatenation of its
ephemeral contents.
In fact, Hume criticised the whole conception of substance for lacking in
empirical content: when you search for the owner of the properties that
make up a substance, you find nothing but further properties.
Consequently, the mind is, he claimed, nothing but a ‘bundle’ or ‘heap’ of
impressions and ideas—that is, of particular mental states or events,
without an owner. This position has been labelled bundle dualism, and it
is a special case of a general bundle theory of substance, according to
which objects in general are just organised collections of properties. The
problem for the Humean is to explain what binds the elements in the
bundle together. This is an issue for any kind of substance, but for
material bodies the solution seems fairly straightforward: the unity of a
physical bundle is constituted by some form of causal interaction between
the elements in the bundle. For the mind, mere causal connection is not
enough; some further relation of co-consciousness is required. We shall
see in 5.2.1 that it is problematic whether one can treat such a relation as
more primitive than the notion of belonging to a subject.
One should note the following about Hume's theory. His bundle theory is
a theory about the nature of the unity of the mind. As a theory about this
unity, it is not necessarily dualist. Parfit (1970, 1984) and Shoemaker
(1984, ch. 2), for example, accept it as physicalists. In general,
physicalists will accept it unless they wish to ascribe the unity to the
brain or the organism as a whole. Before the bundle theory can be dualist
one must accept property dualism, for more about which, see the next
section.
A crisis in the history of dualism came, however, with the growing
popularity of mechanism in science in the nineteenth century. According
to the mechanist, the world is, as it would now be expressed, ‘closed
Dualism
10 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
under physics’. This means that everything that happens follows from and
is in accord with the laws of physics. There is, therefore, no scope for
interference in the physical world by the mind in the way that
interactionism seems to require. According to the mechanist, the
conscious mind is an epiphenomenon (a notion given general currency by
T. H. Huxley 1893): that is, it is a by-product of the physical system
which has no influence back on it. In this way, the facts of consciousness
are acknowledged but the integrity of physical science is preserved.
However, many philosophers found it implausible to claim such things as
the following; the pain that I have when you hit me, the visual sensations
I have when I see the ferocious lion bearing down on me or the conscious
sense of understanding I have when I hear your argument—all have
nothing directly to do with the way I respond. It is very largely due to the
need to avoid this counterintuitiveness that we owe the concern of
twentieth century philosophy to devise a plausible form of materialist
monism. But, although dualism has been out of fashion in psychology
since the advent of behaviourism (Watson 1913) and in philosophy since
Ryle (1949), the argument is by no means over. Some distinguished
neurologists, such as Sherrington (1940) and Eccles (Popper and Eccles
1977) have continued to defend dualism as the only theory that can
preserve the data of consciousness. Amongst mainstream philosophers,
discontent with physicalism led to a modest revival of property dualism in
the last decade of the twentieth century. At least some of the reasons for
this should become clear below.
2. Varieties of Dualism: Ontology
There are various ways of dividing up kinds of dualism. One natural way
is in terms of what sorts of things one chooses to be dualistic about. The
most common categories lighted upon for these purposes are substance
and property, giving one substance dualism and property dualism. There
is, however, an important third category, namely predicate dualism. As
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 11
this last is the weakest theory, in the sense that it claims least, I shall
begin by characterizing it.
2.1 Predicate dualism
Predicate dualism is the theory that psychological or mentalistic
predicates are (a) essential for a full description of the world and (b) are
not reducible to physicalistic predicates. For a mental predicate to be
reducible, there would be bridging laws connecting types of psychological
states to types of physical ones in such a way that the use of the mental
predicate carried no information that could not be expressed without it.
An example of what we believe to be a true type reduction outside
psychology is the case of water, where water is always H
2
O: something is
water if and only if it is H
2
O. If one were to replace the word ‘water’ by
‘H
2
O’, it is plausible to say that one could convey all the same
information. But the terms in many of the special sciences (that is, any
science except physics itself) are not reducible in this way. Not every
hurricane or every infectious disease, let alone every devaluation of the
currency or every coup d'etat has the same constitutive structure. These
states are defined more by what they do than by their composition or
structure. Their names are classified as functional terms rather than
natural kind terms. It goes with this that such kinds of state are multiply
realizable; that is, they may be constituted by different kinds of physical
structures under different circumstances. Because of this, unlike in the
case of water and H
2
O, one could not replace these terms by some more
basic physical description and still convey the same information. There is
no particular description, using the language of physics or chemistry, that
would do the work of the word ‘hurricane’, in the way that ‘H
2
O’ would
do the work of ‘water’. It is widely agreed that many, if not all,
psychological states are similarly irreducible, and so psychological
predicates are not reducible to physical descriptions and one has predicate
dualism. (The classic source for irreducibility in the special sciences in
Dualism
12 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
general is Fodor (1974), and for irreducibility in the philosophy of mind,
Davidson (1971).)
2.2 Property Dualism
Whereas predicate dualism says that there are two essentially different
kinds of predicates in our language, property dualism says that there are
two essentially different kinds of property out in the world. Property
dualism can be seen as a step stronger than predicate dualism. Although
the predicate ‘hurricane’ is not equivalent to any single description using
the language of physics, we believe that each individual hurricane is
nothing but a collection of physical atoms behaving in a certain way: one
need have no more than the physical atoms, with their normal physical
properties, following normal physical laws, for there to be a hurricane.
One might say that we need more than the language of physics to
describe and explain the weather, but we do not need more than its
ontology. There is token identity between each individual hurricane and a
mass of atoms, even if there is no type identity between hurricanes as
kinds and some particular structure of atoms as a kind. Genuine property
dualism occurs when, even at the individual level, the ontology of physics
is not sufficient to constitute what is there. The irreducible language is not
just another way of describing what there is, it requires that there be
something more there than was allowed for in the initial ontology. Until
the early part of the twentieth century, it was common to think that
biological phenomena (‘life’) required property dualism (an irreducible
‘vital force’), but nowadays the special physical sciences other than
psychology are generally thought to involve only predicate dualism. In
the case of mind, property dualism is defended by those who argue that
the qualitative nature of consciousness is not merely another way of
categorizing states of the brain or of behaviour, but a genuinely emergent
phenomenon.
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 13
2.3 Substance Dualism
There are two important concepts deployed in this notion. One is that of
substance, the other is the dualism of these substances. A substance is
characterized by its properties, but, according to those who believe in
substances, it is more than the collection of the properties it possesses, it
is the thing which possesses them. So the mind is not just a collection of
thoughts, but is that which thinks, an immaterial substance over and above
its immaterial states. Properties are the properties of objects. If one is a
property dualist, one may wonder what kinds of objects possess the
irreducible or immaterial properties in which one believes. One can use a
neutral expression and attribute them to persons, but, until one has an
account of person, this is not explanatory. One might attribute them to
human beings qua animals, or to the brains of these animals. Then one
will be holding that these immaterial properties are possessed by what is
otherwise a purely material thing. But one may also think that not only
mental states are immaterial, but that the subject that possesses them must
also be immaterial. Then one will be a dualist about that to which mental
states and properties belong as well about the properties themselves. Now
one might try to think of these subjects as just bundles of the immaterial
states. This is Hume's view. But if one thinks that the owner of these
states is something quite over and above the states themselves, and is
immaterial, as they are, one will be a substance dualist.
Substance dualism is also often dubbed ‘Cartesian dualism’, but some
substance dualists are keen to distinguish their theories from Descartes's.
E. J. Lowe, for example, is a substance dualist, in the following sense. He
holds that a normal human being involves two substances, one a body and
the other a person. The latter is not, however, a purely mental substance
that can be defined in terms of thought or consciousness alone, as
Descartes claimed. But persons and their bodies have different identity
conditions and are both substances, so there are two substances essentially
Dualism
14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
involved in a human being, hence this is a form of substances dualism.
Lowe (2006) claims that his theory is close to P. F. Strawson's (1959),
whilst admitting that Strawson would not have called it substance
dualism.
3. Varieties of Dualism: Interaction
If mind and body are different realms, in the way required by either
property or substance dualism, then there arises the question of how they
are related. Common sense tells us that they interact: thoughts and
feelings are at least sometimes caused by bodily events and at least
sometimes themselves give rise to bodily responses. I shall now consider
briefly the problems for interactionism, and its main rivals,
epiphenomenalism and parallelism.
3.1 Interactionism
Interactionism is the view that mind and body—or mental events and
physical events—causally influence each other. That this is so is one of
our common-sense beliefs, because it appears to be a feature of everyday
experience. The physical world influences my experience through my
senses, and I often react behaviourally to those experiences. My thinking,
too, influences my speech and my actions. There is, therefore, a massive
natural prejudice in favour of interactionism. It has been claimed,
however, that it faces serious problems (some of which were anticipated
in section 1).
The simplest objection to interaction is that, in so far as mental properties,
states or substances are of radically different kinds from each other, they
lack that communality necessary for interaction. It is generally agreed
that, in its most naive form, this objection to interactionism rests on a
‘billiard ball’ picture of causation: if all causation is by impact, how can
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 15
the material and the immaterial impact upon each other? But if causation
is either by a more ethereal force or energy or only a matter of constant
conjunction, there would appear to be no problem in principle with the
idea of interaction of mind and body.
Even if there is no objection in principle, there appears to be a conflict
between interactionism and some basic principles of physical science. For
example, if causal power was flowing in and out of the physical system,
energy would not be conserved, and the conservation of energy is a
fundamental scientific law. Various responses have been made to this.
One suggestion is that it might be possible for mind to influence the
distribution of energy, without altering its quantity. (See Averill and
Keating 1981). Another response is to challenge the relevance of the
conservation principle in this context. The conservation principle states
that ‘in a causally isolated system the total amount of energy will remain
constant’. Whereas ‘[t]he interactionist denies…that the human body is an
isolated system’, so the principle is irrelevant (Larmer (1986), 282: this
article presents a good brief survey of the options).
Robins Collins (2011) has claimed that the appeal to conservation by
opponents of interactionism is something of a red herring because
conservation principles are not ubiquitous in physics. He argues that
energy is not conserved in general relativity, in quantum theory, or in the
universe taken as a whole. Why then, should we insist on it in mind-brain
interaction?
Most discussion of interactionism takes place in the context of the
assumption that it is incompatible with the world's being ‘closed under
physics’. This is a very natural assumption, but it is not justified if causal
overdetermination of behaviour is possible. There could then be a
complete physical cause of behaviour, and a mental one. The strongest
intuitive objection against overdetermination is clearly stated by Mills
Dualism
16 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(1996: 112), who is himself a defender of overdetermination.
For X to be a cause of Y, X must contribute something to Y. The only way
a purely mental event could contribute to a purely physical one would be
to contribute some feature not already determined by a purely physical
event. But if physical closure is true, there is no feature of the purely
physical effect that is not contributed by the purely physical cause. Hence
interactionism violates physical closure after all.
Mills says that this argument is invalid, because a physical event can have
features not explained by the event which is its sufficient cause. For
example, “the rock's hitting the window is causally sufficient for the
window's breaking, and the window's breaking has the feature of being
the third window-breaking in the house this year; but the facts about prior
window-breakings, rather than the rock's hitting the window, are what
cause this window-breaking to have this feature.”
The opponent of overdetermination could perhaps reply that his principle
applies, not to every feature of events, but to a subgroup—say, intrinsic
features, not merely relational or comparative ones. It is this kind of
feature that the mental event would have to cause, but physical closure
leaves no room for this. These matters are still controversial.
The problem with closure of physics may be radically altered if physical
laws are indeterministic, as quantum theory seems to assert. If physical
laws are deterministic, then any interference from outside would lead to a
breach of those laws. But if they are indeterministic, might not
interference produce a result that has a probability greater than zero, and
so be consistent with the laws? This way, one might have interaction yet
preserve a kind of nomological closure, in the sense that no laws are
infringed. Because it involves assessing the significance and
consequences of quantum theory, this is a difficult matter for the non-
physicist to assess. Some argue that indeterminacy manifests itself only
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 17
on the subatomic level, being cancelled out by the time one reaches even
very tiny macroscopic objects: and human behaviour is a macroscopic
phenomenon. Others argue that the structure of the brain is so finely
tuned that minute variations could have macroscopic effects, rather in the
way that, according to ‘chaos theory’, the flapping of a butterfly's wings
in China might affect the weather in New York. (For discussion of this,
see Eccles (1980), (1987), and Popper and Eccles (1977).) Still others
argue that quantum indeterminacy manifests itself directly at a high level,
when acts of observation collapse the wave function, suggesting that the
mind may play a direct role in affecting the state of the world (Hodgson
1988; Stapp 1993).
3.2 Epiphenomenalism
If the reality of property dualism is not to be denied, but the problem of
how the immaterial is to affect the material is to be avoided, then
epiphenomenalism may seem to be the answer. According to this theory,
mental events are caused by physical events, but have no causal influence
on the physical. I have introduced this theory as if its point were to avoid
the problem of how two different categories of thing might interact. In
fact, it is, at best, an incomplete solution to this problem. If it is
mysterious how the non-physical can have it in its nature to influence the
physical, it ought to be equally mysterious how the physical can have it in
its nature to produce something non-physical. But that this latter is what
occurs is an essential claim of epiphenomenalism. (For development of
this point, see Green (2003), 149–51). In fact, epiphenomenalism is more
effective as a way of saving the autonomy of the physical (the world as
‘closed under physics') than as a contribution to avoiding the need for the
physical and non-physical to have causal commerce.
There are at least three serious problems for epiphenomenalism. First, as I
indicated in section 1, it is profoundly counterintuitive. What could be
Dualism
18 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
more apparent than that it is the pain that I feel that makes me cry, or the
visual experience of the boulder rolling towards me that makes me run
away? At least one can say that epiphenomenalism is a fall-back position:
it tends to be adopted because other options are held to be unacceptable.
The second problem is that, if mental states do nothing, there is no reason
why they should have evolved. This objection ties in with the first: the
intuition there was that conscious states clearly modify our behaviour in
certain ways, such as avoiding danger, and it is plain that they are very
useful from an evolutionary perspective.
Frank Jackson (1982) replies to this objection by saying that it is the brain
state associated with pain that evolves for this reason: the sensation is a
by-product. Evolution is full of useless or even harmful by-products. For
example, polar bears have evolved thick coats to keep them warm, even
though this has the damaging side effect that they are heavy to carry.
Jackson's point is true in general, but does not seem to apply very happily
to the case of mind. The heaviness of the polar bear's coat follows
directly from those properties and laws which make it warm: one could
not, in any simple way, have one without the other. But with mental
states, dualistically conceived, the situation is quite the opposite. The laws
of physical nature which, the mechanist says, make brain states cause
behaviour, in no way explain why brain states should give rise to
conscious ones. The laws linking mind and brain are what Feigl (1958)
calls nomological danglers, that is, brute facts added onto the body of
integrated physical law. Why there should have been by-products of that
kind seems to have no evolutionary explanation.
The third problem concerns the rationality of belief in epiphenomenalism,
via its effect on the problem of other minds. It is natural to say that I
know that I have mental states because I experience them directly. But
how can I justify my belief that others have them? The simple version of
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 19
the ‘argument from analogy’ says that I can extrapolate from my own
case. I know that certain of my mental states are correlated with certain
pieces of behaviour, and so I infer that similar behaviour in others is also
accompanied by similar mental states. Many hold that this is a weak
argument because it is induction from one instance, namely, my own. The
argument is stronger if it is not a simple induction but an ‘argument to the
best explanation’. I seem to know from my own case that mental events
can be the explanation of behaviour, and I know of no other candidate
explanation for typical human behaviour, so I postulate the same
explanation for the behaviour of others. But if epiphenomenalism is true,
my mental states do not explain my behaviour and there is a physical
explanation for the behaviour of others. It is explanatorily redundant to
postulate such states for others. I know, by introspection, that I have them,
but is it not just as likely that I alone am subject to this quirk of nature,
rather than that everyone is?
For more detailed treatment and further reading on this topic, see the
entry epiphenomenalism.
3.3 Parallelism
The epiphenomenalist wishes to preserve the integrity of physical science
and the physical world, and appends those mental features that he cannot
reduce. The parallelist preserves both realms intact, but denies all causal
interaction between them. They run in harmony with each other, but not
because their mutual influence keeps each other in line. That they should
behave as if they were interacting would seem to be a bizarre coincidence.
This is why parallelism has tended to be adopted only by those—like
Leibniz—who believe in a pre-established harmony, set in place by God.
The progression of thought can be seen as follows. Descartes believes in a
more or less natural form of interaction between immaterial mind and
material body. Malebranche thought that this was impossible naturally,
Dualism
20 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
and so required God to intervene specifically on each occasion on which
interaction was required. Leibniz decided that God might as well set
things up so that they always behaved as if they were interacting, without
particular intervention being required. Outside such a theistic framework,
the theory is incredible. Even within such a framework, one might well
sympathise with Berkeley's instinct that once genuine interaction is ruled
out one is best advised to allow that God creates the physical world
directly, within the mental realm itself, as a construct out of experience.
4. Arguments for Dualism
4.1 The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism
One category of arguments for dualism is constituted by the standard
objections against physicalism. Prime examples are those based on the
existence of qualia, the most important of which is the so-called
‘knowledge argument’. Because this argument has its own entry (see the
entry qualia: the knowledge argument), I shall deal relatively briefly with
it here. One should bear in mind, however, that all arguments against
physicalism are also arguments for the irreducible and hence immaterial
nature of the mind and, given the existence of the material world, are thus
arguments for dualism.
The knowledge argument asks us to imagine a future scientist who has
lacked a certain sensory modality from birth, but who has acquired a
perfect scientific understanding of how this modality operates in others.
This scientist—call him Harpo—may have been born stone deaf, but
become the world's greatest expert on the machinery of hearing: he knows
everything that there is to know within the range of the physical and
behavioural sciences about hearing. Suppose that Harpo, thanks to
developments in neurosurgery, has an operation which finally enables him
to hear. It is suggested that he will then learn something he did not know
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 21
before, which can be expressed as what it is like to hear, or the qualitative
or phenomenal nature of sound. These qualitative features of experience
are generally referred to as qualia. If Harpo learns something new, he did
not know everything before. He knew all the physical facts before. So
what he learns on coming to hear—the facts about the nature of
experience or the nature of qualia—are non-physical. This establishes at
least a state or property dualism. (See Jackson 1982; Robinson 1982.)
There are at least two lines of response to this popular but controversial
argument. First is the ‘ability’ response. According to this, Harpo does not
acquire any new factual knowledge, only ‘knowledge how’, in the form of
the ability to respond directly to sounds, which he could not do before.
This essentially behaviouristic account is exactly what the intuition
behind the argument is meant to overthrow. Putting ourselves in Harpo's
position, it is meant to be obvious that what he acquires is knowledge of
what something is like, not just how to do something. Such appeals to
intuition are always, of course, open to denial by those who claim not to
share the intuition. Some ability theorists seem to blur the distinction
between knowing what something is like and knowing how to do
something, by saying that the ability Harpo acquires is to imagine or
remember the nature of sound. In this case, what he acquires the ability to
do involves the representation to himself of what the thing is like. But this
conception of representing to oneself, especially in the form of
imagination, seems sufficiently close to producing in oneself something
very like a sensory experience that it only defers the problem: until one
has a physicalist gloss on what constitutes such representations as those
involved in conscious memory and imagination, no progress has been
made.
The other line of response is to argue that, although Harpo's new
knowledge is factual, it is not knowledge of a new fact. Rather, it is new
way of grasping something that he already knew. He does not realise this,
Dualism
22 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
because the concepts employed to capture experience (such as ‘looks red’
or ‘sounds C-sharp’) are similar to demonstratives, and demonstrative
concepts lack the kind of descriptive content that allow one to infer what
they express from other pieces of information that one may already
possess. A total scientific knowledge of the world would not enable you
to say which time was ‘now’ or which place was ‘here’. Demonstrative
concepts pick something out without saying anything extra about it.
Similarly, the scientific knowledge that Harpo originally possessed did
not enable him to anticipate what it would be like to re-express some
parts of that knowledge using the demonstrative concepts that only
experience can give one. The knowledge, therefore, appears to be
genuinely new, whereas only the mode of conceiving it is novel.
Proponents of the epistemic argument respond that it is problematic to
maintain both that the qualitative nature of experience can be genuinely
novel, and that the quality itself be the same as some property already
grasped scientifically: does not the experience's phenomenal nature, which
the demonstrative concepts capture, constitute a property in its own right?
Another way to put this is to say that phenomenal concepts are not pure
demonstratives, like ‘here’ and ‘now’, or ‘this’ and ‘that’, because they do
capture a genuine qualitative content. Furthermore, experiencing does not
seem to consist simply in exercising a particular kind of concept,
demonstrative or not. When Harpo has his new form of experience, he
does not simply exercise a new concept; he also grasps something new—
the phenomenal quality—with that concept. How decisive these
considerations are, remains controversial.
4.2 The Argument from Predicate Dualism to Property Dualism
I said above that predicate dualism might seem to have no ontological
consequences, because it is concerned only with the different way things
can be described within the contexts of the different sciences, not with
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 23
any real difference in the things themselves. This, however, can be
disputed.
The argument from predicate to property dualism moves in two steps,
both controversial. The first claims that the irreducible special sciences,
which are the sources of irreducible predicates, are not wholly objective
in the way that physics is, but depend for their subject matter upon
interest-relative perspectives on the world. This means that they, and the
predicates special to them, depend on the existence of minds and mental
states, for only minds have interest-relative perspectives. The second
claim is that psychology—the science of the mental—is itself an
irreducible special science, and so it, too, presupposes the existence of the
mental. Mental predicates therefore presuppose the mentality that creates
them: mentality cannot consist simply in the applicability of the
predicates themselves.
First, let us consider the claim that the special sciences are not fully
objective, but are interest-relative.
No-one would deny, of course, that the very same subject matter or ‘hunk
of reality’ can be described in irreducibly different ways and it still be just
that subject matter or piece of reality. A mass of matter could be
characterized as a hurricane, or as a collection of chemical elements, or as
mass of sub-atomic particles, and there be only the one mass of matter.
But such different explanatory frameworks seem to presuppose different
perspectives on that subject matter.
This is where basic physics, and perhaps those sciences reducible to basic
physics, differ from irreducible special sciences. On a realist construal,
the completed physics cuts physical reality up at its ultimate joints: any
special science which is nomically strictly reducible to physics also, in
virtue of this reduction, it could be argued, cuts reality at its joints, but
not at its minutest ones. If scientific realism is true, a completed physics
Dualism
24 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
will tell one how the world is, independently of any special interest or
concern: it is just how the world is. It would seem that, by contrast, a
science which is not nomically reducible to physics does not take its
legitimation from the underlying reality in this direct way. Rather, such a
science is formed from the collaboration between, on the one hand,
objective similarities in the world and, on the other, perspectives and
interests of those who devise the science. The concept of hurricane is
brought to bear from the perspective of creatures concerned about the
weather. Creatures totally indifferent to the weather would have no reason
to take the real patterns of phenomena that hurricanes share as
constituting a single kind of thing. With the irreducible special sciences,
there is an issue of salience , which involves a subjective component: a
selection of phenomena with a certain teleology in mind is required
before their structures or patterns are reified. The entities of metereology
or biology are, in this respect, rather like Gestalt phenomena.
Even accepting this, why might it be thought that the perspectivality of
the special sciences leads to a genuine property dualism in the philosophy
of mind? It might seem to do so for the following reason. Having a
perspective on the world, perceptual or intellectual, is a psychological
state. So the irreducible special sciences presuppose the existence of
mind. If one is to avoid an ontological dualism, the mind that has this
perspective must be part of the physical reality on which it has its
perspective. But psychology, it seems to be almost universally agreed, is
one of those special sciences that is not reducible to physics, so if its
subject matter is to be physical, it itself presupposes a perspective and,
hence, the existence of a mind to see matter as psychological. If this mind
is physical and irreducible, it presupposes mind to see it as such. We
seem to be in a vicious circle or regress.
We can now understand the motivation for full-blown reduction. A true
basic physics represents the world as it is in itself, and if the special
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 25
sciences were reducible, then the existence of their ontologies would
make sense as expressions of the physical, not just as ways of seeing or
interpreting it. They could be understood ‘from the bottom up’, not from
top down. The irreducibility of the special sciences creates no problem for
the dualist, who sees the explanatory endeavor of the physical sciences as
something carried on from a perspective conceptually outside of the
physical world. Nor need this worry a physicalist, if he can reduce
psychology, for then he could understand ‘from the bottom up’ the acts
(with their internal, intentional contents) which created the irreducible
ontologies of the other sciences. But psychology is one of the least likely
of sciences to be reduced. If psychology cannot be reduced, this line of
reasoning leads to real emergence for mental acts and hence to a real
dualism for the properties those acts instantiate (Robinson 2003).
4.3 The Modal Argument
There is an argument, which has roots in Descartes (Meditation VI),
which is a modal argument for dualism. One might put it as follows:
1. It is imaginable that one's mind might exist without one's body.
therefore
2. It is conceivable that one's mind might exist without one's body.
therefore
3. It is possible one's mind might exist without one's body.
therefore
4. One's mind is a different entity from one's body.
The rationale of the argument is a move from imaginability to real
Dualism
26 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
possibility. I include (2) because the notion of conceivability has one foot
in the psychological camp, like imaginability, and one in the camp of pure
logical possibility and therefore helps in the transition from one to the
other.
This argument should be distinguished from a similar ‘conceivability’
argument, often known as the ‘zombie hypothesis’, which claims the
imaginability and possibility of my body (or, in some forms, a body
physically just like it) existing without there being any conscious states
associated with it. (See, for example, Chalmers (1996), 94–9.) This latter
argument, if sound, would show that conscious states were something
over and above physical states. It is a different argument because the
hypothesis that the unaltered body could exist without the mind is not the
same as the suggestion that the mind might continue to exist without the
body, nor are they trivially equivalent. The zombie argument establishes
only property dualism and a property dualist might think disembodied
existence inconceivable—for example, if he thought the identity of a
mind through time depended on its relation to a body (e.g., Penelhum
1970).
Before Kripke (1972/80), the first challenge to such an argument would
have concerned the move from (3) to (4). When philosophers generally
believed in contingent identity, that move seemed to them invalid. But
nowadays that inference is generally accepted and the issue concerns the
relation between imaginability and possibility. No-one would nowadays
identify the two (except, perhaps, for certain quasi-realists and anti-
realists), but the view that imaginability is a solid test for possibility has
been strongly defended. W. D. Hart ((1994), 266), for example, argues
that no clear example has been produced such that “one can imagine that p
(and tell less imaginative folk a story that enables them to imagine that p)
plus a good argument that it is impossible that p. No such
counterexamples have been forthcoming…” This claim is at least
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 27
contentious. There seem to be good arguments that time-travel is
incoherent, but every episode of Star-Trek or Doctor Who shows how one
can imagine what it might be like were it possible.
It is worth relating the appeal to possibility in this argument to that
involved in the more modest, anti-physicalist, zombie argument. The
possibility of this hypothesis is also challenged, but all that is necessary
for a zombie to be possible is that all and only the things that the physical
sciences say about the body be true of such a creature. As the concepts
involved in such sciences—e.g., neuron, cell, muscle—seem to make no
reference, explicit or implicit, to their association with consciousness, and
are defined in purely physical terms in the relevant science texts, there is
a very powerful prima facie case for thinking that something could meet
the condition of being just like them and lack any connection with
consciousness. There is no parallel clear, uncontroversial and regimented
account of mental concepts as a whole that fails to invoke, explicitly or
implicitly, physical (e.g., behavioural) states.
For an analytical behaviourist the appeal to imaginability made in the
argument fails, not because imagination is not a reliable guide to
possibility, but because we cannot imagine such a thing, as it is a priori
impossible. The impossibility of disembodiment is rather like that of time
travel, because it is demonstrable a priori, though only by arguments that
are controversial. The argument can only get under way for those
philosophers who accept that the issue cannot be settled a priori, so the
possibility of the disembodiment that we can imagine is still prima facie
open.
A major rationale of those who think that imagination is not a safe
indication of possibility, even when such possibility is not eliminable a
priori, is that we can imagine that a posteriori necessities might be false—
for example, that Hesperus might not be identical to Phosphorus. But if
Dualism
28 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Kripke is correct, that is not a real possibility. Another way of putting this
point is that there are many epistemic possibilities which are imaginable
because they are epistemic possibilities, but which are not real
possibilities. Richard Swinburne (1997, New Appendix C), whilst
accepting this argument in general, has interesting reasons for thinking
that it cannot apply in the mind-body case. He argues that in cases that
involve a posteriori necessities, such as those identities that need
discovering, it is because we identify those entities only by their
‘stereotypes’ (that is, by their superficial features observable by the
layman) that we can be wrong about their essences. In the case of our
experience of ourselves this is not true.
Now it is true that the essence of Hesperus cannot be discovered by a
mere thought experiment. That is because what makes Hesperus Hesperus
is not the stereotype, but what underlies it. But it does not follow that no
one can ever have access to the essence of a substance, but must always
rely for identification on a fallible stereotype. One might think that for the
person him or herself, while what makes that person that person underlies
what is observable to others, it does not underlie what is experienceable
by that person, but is given directly in their own self-awareness.
This is a very appealing Cartesian intuition: my identity as the thinking
thing that I am is revealed to me in consciousness, it is not something
beyond the veil of consciousness. Now it could be replied to this that
though I do access myself as a conscious subject, so classifying myself is
rather like considering myself qua cyclist. Just as I might never have been
a cyclist, I might never have been conscious, if things had gone wrong in
my very early life. I am the organism, the animal, which might not have
developed to the point of consciousness, and that essence as animal is not
revealed to me just by introspection.
But there are vital differences between these cases. A cyclist is explicitly
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 29
presented as a human being (or creature of some other animal species)
cycling: there is no temptation to think of a cyclist as a basic kind of thing
in its own right. Consciousness is not presented as a property of
something, but as the subject itself. Swinburne's claim that when we refer
to ourselves we are referring to something we think we are directly aware
of and not to ‘something we know not what’ that underlies our experience
seemingly ‘of ourselves’ has powerful intuitive appeal and could only be
overthrown by very forceful arguments. Yet, even if we are not referring
primarily to a substrate, but to what is revealed in consciousness, could it
not still be the case that there is a necessity stronger than causal
connecting this consciousness to something physical? To consider this
further we must investigate what the limits are of the possible analogy
between cases of the water-H
2
O kind, and the mind-body relation.
We start from the analogy between the water stereotype—how water
presents itself—and how consciousness is given first-personally to the
subject. It is plausible to claim that something like water could exist
without being H
2
O, but hardly that it could exist without some underlying
nature. There is, however, no reason to deny that this underlying nature
could be homogenous with its manifest nature: that is, it would seem to be
possible that there is a world in which the water-like stuff is an element,
as the ancients thought, and is water-like all the way down. The claim of
the proponents of the dualist argument is that this latter kind of situation
can be known to be true a priori in the case of the mind: that is, one can
tell by introspection that it is not more-than-causally dependent on
something of a radically different nature, such as a brain or body. What
grounds might one have for thinking that one could tell that a priori?
The only general argument that seem to be available for this would be the
principle that, for any two levels of discourse, A and B, they are more-
than-causally connected only if one entails the other a priori. And the
argument for accepting this principle would be that the relatively
Dualism
30 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
uncontroversial cases of a posteriori necessary connections are in fact
cases in which one can argue a priori from facts about the microstructure
to the manifest facts. In the case of water, for example, it would be
claimed that it follows a priori that if there were something with the
properties attributed to H
2
O by chemistry on a micro level, then that thing
would possess waterish properties on a macro level. What is established a
posteriori is that it is in fact H
2
O that underlies and explains the waterish
properties round here, not something else: the sufficiency of the base—
were it to obtain—to explain the phenomena, can be deduced a priori
from the supposed nature of the base. This is, in effect, the argument that
Chalmers uses to defend the zombie hypothesis. The suggestion is that the
whole category of a posteriori more-than-causally necessary connections
(often identified as a separate category of metaphysical necessity) comes
to no more than this. If we accept that this is the correct account of a
posteriori necessities, and also deny the analytically reductionist theories
that would be necessary for a priori connections between mind and body,
as conceived, for example, by the behaviourist or the functionalist, does it
follow that we can tell a priori that consciousness is not more-than-
causally dependent on the body?
It is helpful in considering this question to employ a distinction like
Berkeley's between ideas and notions. Ideas are the objects of our mental
acts, and they capture transparently—‘by way of image or likeness'
(Principles, sect. 27)—that of which they are the ideas. The self and its
faculties are not the objects of our mental acts, but are captured only
obliquely in the performance of its acts, and of these Berkeley says we
have notions, meaning by this that what we capture of the nature of the
dynamic agent does not seem to have the same transparency as what we
capture as the normal objects of the agent's mental acts. It is not necessary
to become involved in Berkeley's metaphysics in general to feel the force
of the claim that the contents and internal objects of our mental acts are
grasped with a lucidity that exceeds that of our grasp of the agent and the
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 31
acts per se. Because of this, notions of the self perhaps have a ‘thickness’
and are permanently contestable: there seems always to be room for more
dispute as to what is involved in that concept. (Though we shall see later,
in 5.2.2, that there is a ‘non-thick’ way of taking the Berkeleyan concept
of a notion.)
Because ‘thickness’ always leaves room for dispute, this is one of those
cases in philosophy in which one is at the mercy of the arguments
philosophers happen to think up. The conceivability argument creates a
prima facie case for thinking that mind has no more than causal
ontological dependence on the body. Let us assume that one rejects
analytical (behaviourist or functionalist) accounts of mental predicates.
Then the above arguments show that any necessary dependence of mind
on body does not follow the model that applies in other scientific cases.
This does not show that there may not be other reasons for believing in
such dependence, for so many of the concepts in the area are still
contested. For example, it might be argued that identity through time
requires the kind of spatial existence that only body can give: or that the
causal continuity required by a stream of consciousness cannot be a
property of mere phenomena. All these might be put forward as ways of
filling out those aspects of our understanding of the self that are only
obliquely, not transparently, presented in self-awareness. The dualist must
respond to any claim as it arises: the conceivability argument does not
pre-empt them.
4.4 Arguments from Personal Identity
There is a long tradition, dating at least from Reid (1785/1969), for
arguing that the identity of persons over time is not a matter of
convention or degree in the way that the identity of other (complex)
substances is and that this shows that the self is a different kind of entity
from any physical body. Criticism of these arguments and of the intuitions
Dualism
32 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
on which they rest, running from Hume to Parfit (1970: 1984), have left
us with an inconclusive clash of intuitions. The argument under
consideration and which, possibly, has its first statement in Madell
(1981), does not concern identity through time, but the consequences for
identity of certain counterfactuals concerning origin. It can, perhaps,
therefore, break the stalemate which faces the debate over diachronic
identity. The claim is that the broadly conventionalist ways which are
used to deal with problem cases through time for both persons and
material objects, and which can also be employed in cases of
counterfactuals concerning origin for bodies, cannot be used for similar
counterfactuals concerning persons or minds.
Concerning ordinary physical objects, it is easy to imagine counterfactual
cases where questions of identity become problematic. Take the example
of a particular table. We can scale counterfactual suggestions as follows:
i. This table might have been made of ice.
ii. This table might have been made of a different sort of wood.
iii. This table might have been made of 95% of the wood it was made of
and 5% of some other wood.
The first suggestion would normally be rejected as clearly false, but there
will come a point along the spectrum illustrated by (i) and (iii) and
towards (iii) where the question of whether the hypothesised table would
be the same as the one that actually exists have no obvious answer. It
seems that the question of whether it ‘really’ is the same one has no clear
meaning: it is of, say, 75% the same matter and of 25% different matter;
these are the only genuine facts in the case; the question of numerical
identity can be decided in any convenient fashion, or left unresolved.
There will thus be a penumbra of counterfactual cases where the question
of whether two things would be the same is not a matter of fact.
Let us now apply this thought to conscious subjects. Suppose that a given
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 33
human individual had had origins different from those which he in fact
had such that whether that difference affected who he was was not
obvious to intuition. What would count as such a case might be a matter
of controversy, but there must be one. Perhaps it is unclear whether, if
there had been a counterpart to Jones' body from the same egg but a
different though genetically identical sperm from the same father, the
person there embodied would have been Jones. Some philosophers might
regard it as obvious that sameness of sperm is essential to the identity of a
human body and to personal identity. In that case imagine a counterpart
sperm in which some of the molecules in the sperm are different; would
that be the same sperm? If one pursues the matter far enough there will be
indeterminacy which will infect that of the resulting body. There must
therefore be some difference such that neither natural language nor
intuition tells us whether the difference alters the identity of the human
body; a point, that is, where the question of whether we have the same
body is not a matter of fact.
How one is to describe these cases is, in some respects, a matter of
controversy. Some philosophers think one can talk of vague identity or
partial identity. Others think that such expressions are nonsensical. There
is no space to discuss this issue here. It is enough to assume, however,
that questions of how one is allowed to use the concept of identity effect
only the care with which one should characterize these cases, not any
substantive matter of fact. There are cases of substantial overlap of
constitution in which that fact is the only bedrock fact in the case: there is
no further fact about whether they are ‘really’ the same object. If there
were, then there would have to be a haecceitas or thisness belonging to
and individuating each complex physical object, and this I am assuming to
be implausible if not unintelligible. (More about the conditions under
which haecceitas can make sense will be found below.)
One might plausibly claim that no similar overlap of constitution can be
Dualism
34 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
applied to the counterfactual identity of minds. In Geoffrey Madell's
(1981) words:
Why is this so? Imagine the case where we are not sure whether it would
have been Jones' body—and, hence, Jones—that would have been created
by the slightly modified sperm and the same egg. Can we say, as we
would for an object with no consciousness, that the story something the
same, something different is the whole story: that overlap of constitution
is all there is to it? For the Jones body as such, this approach would do as
well as for any other physical object. But suppose Jones, in reflective
mood, asks himself ‘if that had happened, would I have existed?’ There
are at least three answers he might give to himself. (i) I either would or
would not, but I cannot tell. (ii) There is no fact of the matter whether I
would or would not have existed: it is just a mis-posed question. (iii) In
some ways, or to some degree, I would have, and in some ways, or to
some degree, I would not. The creature who would have existed would
have had a kind of overlap of psychic constitution with me.
The third answer parallels the response we would give in the case of
bodies. But as an account of the subjective situation, it is arguable that
this makes no sense. Call the creature that would have emerged from the
slightly modified sperm, ‘Jones2’. Is the overlap suggestion that, just as,
say 85% of Jones2's original body would have been identical with Jones',
about 85% of his psychic life would have been Jones'? That it would have
been like Jones'—indeed that Jones2 might have had a psychic life 100%
like Jones'—makes perfect sense, but that he might have been to that
degree, the same psyche—that Jones ‘85% existed’ —arguably makes no
But while my present body can thus have its partial counterpart in
some possible world, my present consciousness cannot. Any
present state of consciousness that I can imagine either is or is not
mine. There is no question of degree here. (91)
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 35
sense. Take the case in which Jones and Jones2 have exactly similar lives
throughout: which 85% of the 100% similar mental events do they share?
Nor does it make sense to suggest that Jones might have participated in
the whole of Jones2's psychic life, but in a rather ghostly only 85% there
manner. Clearly, the notion of overlap of numerically identical psychic
parts cannot be applied in the way that overlap of actual bodily part
constitution quite unproblematically can.
This might make one try the second answer. We can apply the ‘overlap’
answer to the Jones body, but the question of whether the minds or
subjects would have been the same, has no clear sense. It is difficult to
see why it does not. Suppose Jones found out that he had originally been
one of twins, in the sense that the zygote from which he developed had
divided, but that the other half had died soon afterwards. He can entertain
the thought that if it had been his half that had died, he would never have
existed as a conscious being, though someone would whose life, both
inner and outer, might have been very similar to his. He might feel rather
guiltily grateful that it was the other half that died. It would be strange to
think that Jones is wrong to think that there is a matter of fact about this.
And how is one to ‘manage’ the transition from the case where there is a
matter of fact to the case where there is not?
If the reasoning above is correct, one is left with only the first option. If
so, there has to be an absolute matter of fact from the subjective point of
view. But the physical examples we have considered show that when
something is essentially complex, this cannot be the case. When there is
constitution, degree and overlap of constitution are inevitably possible. So
the mind must be simple, and this is possible only if it is something like a
Cartesian substance.
4.5 The Aristotelian Argument in a Modern Form
Putting his anti-materialist argument outlined above, in section 1, in very
Dualism
36 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
general terms, Aristotle's worry was that a material organ could not have
the range and flexibility that are required for human thought. His worries
concerned the cramping effect that matter would have on the range of
objects that intellect could accommodate. Parallel modern concerns centre
on the restriction that matter would impose on the range of rational
processes that we could exhibit. Godel, for example, believed that his
famous theorem showed that there are demonstrably rational forms of
mathematical thought of which humans are capable which could not be
exhibited by a mechanical or formal system of a sort that a physical mind
would have to be. Penrose (1990) has argued that Turing's halting
problem has similar consequences. In general, the fear is that the
materialist monist has to treat the organ of thought as, what Dennett
(1987:61) calls, a syntactic engine: that is, as something that operates
without any fundamental reference to the propositional content of what it
thinks. It works as a machine that only shadows the pattern of meaning.
But it is hard to convince oneself that, as one, for example, reflectively
discusses philosophy and struggles to follow what is being said, that it is
not the semantic content that is driving one's responses. But if we are
truly semantic engines, it is difficult to see how we can avoid at least a
property dualism. These issues are, of course, connected with problems
raised by Brentano, concerning the irreducibility of intentionality. Despite
the interest of the arguments for dualism based on the irreducible
flexibility of intellect, most of the modern debate turns on arguments that
have a Cartesian origin.
5. Problems for Dualism
We have already discussed the problem of interaction. In this section we
shall consider two other facets of dualism that worry critics. First, there is
what one might term the queerness of the mental if conceived of as non-
physical. Second there is the difficulty of giving an account of the unity
of the mind. We shall consider this latter as it faces both the bundle
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 37
theorist and the substance dualist.
5.1 The Queerness of the Mental
Mental states are characterised by two main properties, subjectivity,
otherwise known as privileged access, and intentionality. Physical objects
and their properties are sometimes observable and sometimes not, but any
physical object is equally accessible, in principle, to anyone. From the
right location, we could all see the tree in the quad, and, though none of
us can observe an electron directly, everyone is equally capable of
detecting it in the same ways using instruments. But the possessor of
mental states has a privileged access to them that no-one else can share.
That is why there is a sceptical ‘problem of other minds’, but no
corresponding ‘problem of my own mind’. This suggests to some
philosophers that minds are not ordinary occupants of physical space.
Physical objects are spatio-temporal, and bear spatio-temporal and causal
relations to each other. Mental states seem to have causal powers, but
they also possess the mysterious property of intentionality—being about
other things—including things like Zeus and the square root of minus one,
which do not exist. No mere physical thing could be said to be, in a literal
sense, ‘about’ something else. The nature of the mental is both queer and
elusive. In Ryle's deliberately abusive phrase, the mind, as the dualist
conceives of it, is a ‘ghost in a machine’. Ghosts are mysterious and
unintelligible: machines are composed of identifiable parts and work on
intelligible principles. But this contrast holds only if we stick to a
Newtonian and common-sense view of the material. Think instead of
energy and force-fields in a space-time that possesses none of the
properties that our senses seem to reveal: on this conception, we seem to
be able to attribute to matter nothing beyond an abstruse mathematical
structure. Whilst the material world, because of its mathematicalisation,
forms a tighter abstract system than mind, the sensible properties that
Dualism
38 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
figure as the objects of mental states constitute the only intelligible
content for any concrete picture of the world that we can devise. Perhaps
the world within the experiencing mind is, once one considers it properly,
no more—or even less—queer than the world outside it.
5.2 The Unity of the Mind
Whether one believes that the mind is a substance or just a bundle of
properties, the same challenge arises, which is to explain the nature of the
unity of the immaterial mind. For the Cartesian, that means explaining
how he understands the notion of immaterial substance. For the Humean,
the issue is to explain the nature of the relationship between the different
elements in the bundle that binds them into one thing. Neither tradition
has been notably successful in this latter task: indeed, Hume, in the
appendix to the Treatise, declared himself wholly mystified by the
problem, rejecting his own initial solution (though quite why is not clear
from the text).
5.2.1 Unity and Bundle Dualism
If the mind is only a bundle of properties, without a mental substance to
unite them, then an account is needed of what constitutes its unity. The
only route appears to be to postulate a primitive relation of co-
consciousness in which the various elements stand to each other.
There are two strategies which can be used to attack the bundle theory.
One is to claim that our intuitions favour belief in a subject and that the
arguments presented in favour of the bundle alternative are unsuccessful,
so the intuition stands. The other is to try to refute the theory itself. Foster
(1991, 212–9) takes the former path. This is not effective against
someone who thinks that metaphysical economy gives a prima facie
priority to bundle theories, on account of their avoiding mysterious
substances.
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 39
The core objection to bundle theories (see, for example, Armstrong
(1968), 21–3) is that, because it takes individual mental contents as its
elements, such contents should be able to exist alone, as could the
individual bricks from a house. Hume accepted this consequence, but
most philosophers regard it as absurd. There could not be a mind that
consisted of a lone pain or red after-image, especially not of one that had
detached itself from the mind to which it had previously belonged.
Therefore it makes more sense to think of mental contents as modes of a
subject.
Bundle theorists tend to take phenomenal contents as the primary
elements in their bundle. Thus the problem is how to relate, say, the
visual field to the auditory field, producing a ‘unity of apperception’, that
is, a total experience that seems to be presented to a single subject. Seeing
the problem in this way has obvious Humean roots. This atomistic
conception of the problem becomes less natural if one tries to
accommodate other kinds of mental activity and contents. How are acts of
conceptualising, attending to or willing with respect to, such perceptual
contents to be conceived? These kinds of mental acts seem to be less
naturally treated as atomic elements in a bundle, bound by a passive unity
of apperception. William James (1890, vol. 1, 336–41) attempts to answer
these problems. He claims to introspect in himself a ‘pulse of thought’ for
each present moment, which he calls ‘the Thought’ and which is the
‘vehicle of the judgement of identity’ and the ‘vehicle of choice as well as
of cognition’. These ‘pulses’ are united over time because each
‘appropriates’ the past Thoughts and ‘makes us say “as sure as I exist,
those past facts were part of myself”. James attributes to these Thoughts
acts of judging, attending, willing etc, and this may seem incoherent in
the absence of a genuine subject. But there is also a tendency to treat
many if not all aspects of agency as mere awareness of bodily actions or
tendencies, which moves one back towards a more normal Humean
Dualism
40 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
position. Whether James' position really improves on Hume's, or merely
mystifies it, is still a moot point. (But see Sprigge (1993), 84–97, for an
excellent, sympathetic discussion.)
5.2.2 Unity and Substance Dualism
The problem is to explain what kind of a thing an immaterial substance is,
such that its presence explains the unity of the mind. The answers given
can be divided into three kinds.
(a) The ‘ectoplasm’ account: The view that immaterial substance is a kind
of immaterial stuff. There are two problems with this approach. First, in
so far as this ‘ectoplasm’ has any characterisation as a ‘stuff’—that is, a
structure of its own over and above the explicitly mental properties that it
sustains—it leaves it as much a mystery why this kind of stuff should
support consciousness as it is why ordinary matter should. Second, and
connectedly, it is not clear in what sense such stuff is immaterial, except
in the sense that it cannot be integrated into the normal scientific account
of the physical world. Why is it not just an aberrant kind of physical
stuff?
(b) The ‘consciousness' account: The view that consciousness is the
substance. Account (a) allowed the immaterial substance to have a nature
over and above the kinds of state we would regard as mental. The
consciousness account does not. This is Descartes' view. The most
obvious objection to this theory is that it does not allow the subject to
exist when unconscious. This forces one to take one of four possible
theories. One could claim (i) that we are conscious when we do not seem
to be (which was Descartes' view): or (ii) that we exist intermittently,
though are still the same thing (which is Swinburne's theory, (1997),
179): or (iii) that each of us consists of a series of substances, changed at
any break in consciousness, which pushes one towards a constructivist
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 41
account of identity through time and so towards the spirit of the bundle
theory: or (iv) even more speculatively, that the self stands in such a
relation to the normal time series that its own continued existence is not
brought into question by its failure to be present in time at those moments
when it is not conscious within that series (Robinson, forthcoming).
(c) The ‘no-analysis' account: The view that it is a mistake to present any
analysis. This is Foster's view, though I think Vendler (1984) and Madell
(1981) have similar positions. Foster argues that even the ‘consciousness’
account is an attempt to explain what the immaterial self is ‘made of’
which assimilates it too far towards a kind of physical substance. In other
words, Descartes has only half escaped from the ‘ectoplasmic’ model. (He
has half escaped because he does not attribute non-mental properties to
the self, but he is still captured by trying to explain what it is made of.)
Foster (1991) expresses it as follows:
…it seems to me that when I focus on myself introspectively, I am
not only aware of being in a certain mental condition; I am also
aware, with the same kind of immediacy, of being a certain sort of
thing…
It will now be asked: ‘Well, what is this nature, this sortal
attribute? Let's have it specified!’ But such a demand is
misconceived. Of course, I can give it a verbal label: for instance,
I can call it ‘subjectness’ or ‘selfhood’. But unless they are
interpreted ‘ostensively’, by reference to what is revealed by
introspective awareness, such labels will not convey anything over
and above the nominal essence of the term ‘basic subject’. In this
respect, however, there is no difference between this attribute,
which constitutes the subject's essential nature, and the specific
psychological attributes of his conscious life…
Dualism
42 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Berkeley's concept of notion again helps here. One can interpret Berkeley
as implying that there is more to the self than introspection can capture, or
we can interpret him as saying that notions, though presenting stranger
entities than ideas, capture them just as totally. The latter is the ‘no
account is needed’ view.
Bibliography
Almog, J. (2001): What am I? Descartes and the Mind-Body Problem,
Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Aquinas, St Thomas (1912): Summa Theologica, Washbourne, London.
Aristotle, De Anima, Bk III, D.W. Hamlyn (trans.), Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1968/1993.
Armstrong, D. M. (1968): A Materialist Theory of the Mind, Routledge
and Kegan Paul, ch. 2.
Averill, E. W. and Keating, B. (1981): ‘Does interactionism violate a law
of classical physics?’, Mind 90, 102–7.
Ayer, A. J. (1963): ‘The concept of a person’, in The Concept of a Person
and other Essays, Macmillan, London, 82–128.
Baker, M. C. and Goetz, S. (eds) (2011): The Soul Hypothesis,
Continuum, London.
Berkeley, G. (1710 / 1949): Principles of Human Knowledge in A.A.
Luce and T.E. Jessop (eds.), The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop
of Cloyne, Vol. 2, pp. 41–113, London: Thomas Nelson and Sons.
Bricke, J. (1975): ‘Interaction and physiology’, Mind 84, 255–9.
Broad, C. D. (1925): The Mind and its Place in Nature, Routledge and
Admittedly, the feeling that there must be more to be said from a
God's eye view dies hard. The reason is that, even when we have
acknowledged that basic subjects are wholly non-physical, we still
tend to approach the issue of their essential natures in the shadow
of the physical paradigm. (243–5)
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 43
Kegan Paul, London.
Chalmers, D. (1996): The Conscious Mind, Oxford University Press, New
York.
Collins, C. (1997): ‘Searle on consciousness and dualism’, International
Journal of Philosophical Studies 5, 15–33.
Collins, R. (2011): ‘Energy of the soul’, in Baker, (2011).
Crane, T. (2003): ‘Mental substances’. In A. O'Hear (ed.) Minds and
Persons, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Davidson, D. (1971): ‘Mental events', in L. Foster and J. W. Swanson
(eds) Experience and Theory, Duckworth, London.
Dennett, D, (1987): ‘Three kinds of intentional psychology’, in The
Intentional Stance, MIT Press, Cambridge Mass., 43–68.
Descartes, R. (1641 / 1996): ‘Meditation VI’, in Meditations on the First
Philosophy, J. Cottingham (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Ducasse, C, (1961): ‘In defence of dualism’, in S. Hook (ed.) Dimensions
of Mind, Collier, New York, 85–9.
Eccles, J. (1980): The Human Psyche, Springer, New York.
–––. (1987): ‘Brain and mind: two or one?’ In C. Blakemore and S Green
fields, (eds) Mindwaves, Blackwell, Oxford.
Efron, A. (1992): ‘Residual asymmetric dualism: a theory of mind-body
relations’, Journal of Mind and Behaviour 13, 113–36.
Feigl, H. (1958): ‘The “mental” and the “physical”’, in H. Feigl, M.
Scriven and G. Maxwell, (eds) Concepts, Theories and the Mind-
Body Problem: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol.
2, Minnesota University Press, Minneapolis, 370–497.
Fodor, J. (1974): ‘Special sciences and the disunity of science as a
working hypothesis', Synthese, 28, 77–115.
Foster, J. (1968): ‘Psycho-physical causal relations’, American
Philosophical Quarterly 5.
–––. (1989): ‘A defence of dualism’, in J. Smythies and J. Beloff, (eds),
The Case for Dualism, University of Virginia Press.
Dualism
44 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
–––. (1991): The Immaterial Self, Routledge.
Green, C. (2003): The Lost Cause, Oxford Forum.
Hamlyn, D. W. (1978): ‘Aristotle's Cartesianism’, Paedia: Special
Aristotle Issue, 8–15.
Hart, W. D. (1988): Engines of the Soul, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
–––. (1994): ‘Dualism’, in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the
Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, 265–7.
Hawthorne, J. (2007): ‘Cartesian dualism’. In P. van Inwagen and D.
Zimmerman (eds), Persons Human and Divine, Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
Heil, J. (1998): Philosophy of Mind, Routledge, London and New York,
Ch. 2, ‘Descartes's legacy’.
Herbert, R. T. (1998): ‘Dualism/materialism’, Philosophical Quarterly
48, 159–75.
Himma, K. E. (2005): ‘When a problem for all is a problem for none:
substance dualism, physicalism and the mind-body problem’,
Australian Journal of Philosophy
Hodgson, D. (1988): The Mind Matters: Consciousness and Choice in a
Quantum World, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Honderich, T. (1981): ‘Psychophysical law-like connections and their
problems’, Inquiry 24, 277–303.
Hume, D. (1739 / 2000): A Treatise of Human Nature, Bk I, Pt IV, sect.
VI, and Appendix, D.F. Norton and M.J. Norton (eds.), Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Huxley, T. H. (1893): ‘On the hypothesis that animals are automata’,
Collected Essays, vol. 1, New York, 199–250.
Jackson, F. (1982): ‘Epiphenomenal qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly,
127–136.
James, W. (1890): Principles of Psychology, Macmillan, London.
Kenny, Anthony (1989): The Metaphysics of Mind, Clarendon Press,
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 45
Oxford.
Kim, J. (2003): ‘Lonely souls: causality and substance dualism’. In T.
O'Connor and D. Robb (eds), Philosophy of Mind:contemporary
readings, Routledge, London.
Kripke, S. (1980): Naming and Necessity, Blackwell, Oxford.
Lahav, R. and Shanks, N. (1982): ‘How to be a scientifically respectable
“property dualist”’, Journal of Mind and Behaviour 13, 211–32.
Larmer, R. (1986): ‘Mind-body interactionism and the conservation of
energy’, International Philosophical Quarterly 26, 277–85.
Latham, N. (2000): ‘Chalmers on the addition of consciousness to the
physical world’, Philosophical Studies 98, 67–93.
Lowe, E. J. (1992): ‘The problem of psychophysical causation’,
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70, 263–76.
–––. (1993): ‘The causal autonomy of the mental’ Mind 102, 629–44.
–––. (1996): Subjects of Experience, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
–––. (2006): ‘Non-Cartesian substance dualism and the problem of mental
causation’. Erkenntnis 65 (1): 5–23.
McGinn, C. (1993): ‘Consciousness and cosmology: hyperdualism
ventilated’, in M. Davies and G. Humphreys, (eds), Consciousness:
Psychological and Philosophical Essays, Blackwell.
Madell, G. (1981): The Identity of the Self, Edinburgh University Press,
Edinburgh.
Mills, E. (1996): ‘Interaction and overdetermination’, American
Philosophical Quarterly, 33, 105–15.
–––. (1997): ‘Interactionism and physicality’, Ratio 10, 169–83.
Nussbaum, M. C. (1984): ‘Aristotelian dualism’, Oxford Studies in
Ancient Philosophy, 2, 197–207.
Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (1992): Essays on Aristotle's De
Anima, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
O'Leary-Hawthorne, J. and McDonough, J. K. (1998): ‘Numbers, minds
and bodies: a fresh look at mind-body dualism’, Philosophical
Dualism
46 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Perspectives 12, 349–71.
Oderberg, D. S. (2005): ‘Hylemorphic dualism’, Social Philosophy and
Policy 22, 70–99.
Parfit, D. (1971): ‘Personal identity’, Philosophical Review 80, 3–27.
–––. (1984): Reasons and Persons, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
Penelhum, T. (1970): Survival and Disembodies Existence, Routledge and
Kegan Paul, London.
Penfield, W. (1975): The Mystery of the Mind, Princeton University Press,
Princeton NJ.
Penrose, R. (1990): The Emperor's New Mind, Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Pietroski, P. M. (1994): ‘Mental causation for dualists’, Mind and
Language 9, 336–66.
Plato, Phaedo in J. Cooper (ed.) Plato: Complete Works, pp. 49–100,
Indianapolis: Hackett.
Popper, K. R. (1953): ‘Language and the mind-body problem: a
restatement of interactionism’, in Proceedings of the 11th
International Congress of Philosophy. Reprinted (1962) in
Conjectures and Refutations, Basic Books.
–––. (1955): ‘A note on the mind-body problem’, Analysis 15, 131–5.
Popper, K. and Eccles, J. (1977): The Self and its Brain, Springer, New
York.
Reid, T. (1969): ‘Concerning memory’, in Essays on the Intellectual
Powers of Man, M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, Mass.. First published,
1785.
Richardson, R. C. (1982): ‘The ‘scandal’ of Cartesian dualism’, Mind 91,
20–37.
Robinson, H. (1982): Matter and Sense, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
–––. (1983): ‘Aristotelian dualism’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy
1, 123–44.
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 47
–––. (2003): ‘Dualism’, in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds) The Blackwell
Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford, 85–101.
–––. (forthcoming): ‘Personal identity, self and time’, in A. Batthany (ed.)
Mind: its Place in the World. Non-reductionist Approaches to the
Ontology of Consciousness, Vienna.
Rosenburg, J. F. (1988): ‘On not knowing who or what one is: reflections
on the intelligibility of dualism’, Topoi 7, 57–63.
Rozemond, M. (2002): Descartes's Dualism, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
Ryle, G. (1949): The Concept of Mind, Hutchinson, London, esp. ch. 1.
Sellars, W. (1954): ‘A note on Popper's argument for dualism’, Analysis
15, 23–4.
Sherrington, C. S. (1942): Man on his Nature, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Shoemaker, S. (1984): Identity, Cause, and Mind, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Smook, R. (1988): ‘Egoicity and Twins’, Dialogue, 27, 277–86.
Smythies, J. R. and Beloff, J, (eds) (1989): The Case for Dualism,
University of Virginia Press.
Sprigge, T. L. S. (1993): James and Bradley: American Truth and British
Reality, Open Court, Chicago.
–––. (1994): ‘Consciousness’, Synthese 98, 73–93.
Stapp, H. P. (1993): Mind, Matter, and Quantum Mechanics, Springer-
Verlag, Berlin.
Strawson, P. F. (1959): Individuals, Methuen, London.
Sussman, A. (1981): ‘Reflections on the chances for a scientific dualism’,
Journal of Philosophy 78, 95–118.
Swinburne, R. (1986): The Evolution of the Soul, Clarendon Press,
Oxford. Revised edition (1997).
Taliaferro, C. (1996): Consciousness and the Mind of God, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Vendler, Z. (1972): Res Cogitans, Cornell University Press, Ithaca.
Dualism
48 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
–––. (1984): The Matter of Minds, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
von Rooijen, K. (1987): ‘Interactionism and evolution: a critique of
Popper’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38, 87–92.
von Wright, G. H. (1994): ‘On mind and matter’, Journal of Theoretical
Biology 171, 101–10.
Watson, J. B. (1913): ‘Psychology as the behaviourist views it’,
Psychological Review, vol. 20, 158–77.
Zimmerman, D. W. (2004): ‘Should a Christian be a mind-body dualist?’.
In Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion, Blackwell,
Malden MA.
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Online Papers on Materialism and Dualism List maintained by David
Chalmers.
Mind and body, René Descartes to William James By Robert H.
Wozniak, Bryn Mawr
Related Entries
Aquinas, Saint Thomas | Aristotle | behaviorism | consciousness |
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP
Society.
Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology
Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links
to its database.
Howard Robinson
Winter 2012 Edition 49
Descartes, René | epiphenomenalism | functionalism | haecceity: medieval
theories of | Hume, David | James, William | materialism: eliminative |
mental causation | mind/brain identity theory | neutral monism | personal
identity | physicalism | Plato | qualia | qualia: knowledge argument |
vagueness
Copyright © 2012 by the author
Howard Robinson
Dualism
50 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy